Teaching Portfolio
Teaching Statement
I wanted to be a teacher even before I knew I wanted to be a philosopher. What interested me about teaching was not merely being a font of information, but being a coach that helps students see the world in a different way. The best history teachers I've had didn't just tell me stories about the Battle of Midway or Eleanor of Aquitaine; they led me to see the world as an historian. It has been my goal to show students how to see the issues and subjects we discuss as philosophers. It is, of course, necessary to develop the foundation with facts, figures, and arguments, but those by themselves are insufficient. Students need to feel a sense of engagement, so they come to feel that philosophy matters and are motivated to develop philosophical skills and sensitivities. By focusing, in particular, on this sense of engagement, I have seen students who no one ever expected to become interested in philosophy stay after class to talk about Hobbes and Locke, Mill and Rawls.
I learned to focus on students' active engagement in their own learning well before I began graduate school. Despite the fact that my undergraduate institution had no education degree or certification program, I felt strongly enough about teaching to overcome bureaucratic inertia. Through a combination of independent study and coursework at the Graduate School of Education, I was able to squeeze sufficient pedagogical theory and student teaching into my schedule to be certified as a high school teacher. Then, I taught high school Civics and American Government in South Boston and Chicago. This was an invaluable experience, through which I learned how to engage students who were the least likely and the least willing to care about abstract issues of justice and ethics.
I began teaching at a public high school in South Boston, where I decided to supplement the standard American Government course with some political philosophy, including works by Hobbes and Locke. My mentor teacher (an 18 year veteran of the school) was skeptical about this approach, but open to the idea. I quickly learned to avoid lectures except when absolutely necessary. Unsupervised group time would also be ineffective at the high school level, and asking them to read long passages without philosophical training would simply lead to confusion and resistance. Instead, I gave them structured group work where I selected important passages and asked them to answer questions as a group. These questions helped guide the students through each step of the argument, and at the same time I could circulate amongst them to make sure they remained on task. Finally, after completing the guided work, I asked each group to give a presentation to the rest of the class that showed the relevance of their topic to our subject matter. For example, a group studying an excerpt of Locke had to show the relevance of his ideas to the Declaration of Independence. This was a multi-day lesson, but the students were enthusiastic, as was seen in one group's raucous skit about Hobbes' state of nature. My mentor teacher was pleasantly surprised by the students' reception of this approach. I allowed the students to be responsible for their own instruction and their own learning, but I did not simply leave them unattended to figure it out for themselves. The success of the lessons demonstrates the importance of allowing students to take control of their learning while the teacher serves as mediator and guide.
As a teaching assistant, I've taken that lesson to heart. While I generally eschew lecturing, I rely on it more than I did with high school students. However, even with college students, I make my lecturing as active as possible. First, I provide handouts that follow the structure of my lecture through leading questions, rather than outlining. Thus, the students are forced to remain engaged with the lecture if they want the advantages of the handout. The handouts also mimic the analyses of arguments that I ask them to do when they write papers by asking questions such as, "Why is this premise attractive?" and "What are some possible objections to this move?" These questions serve as the foundation for further discussion by the class. Furthermore, I prime students by having them submit questions in advance either by email or on the class website. Each step is designed to get students to think about the argument themselves, and help prepare them for when they will have to do this sort of analysis on their own in a paper or on an exam. They are asked and required to make a positive contribution even in those cases where they might normally expect to be passive.
I find that these methods, particularly when they can be connected with real world experience, help students both retain information and develop their argumentative skills. For example, when teaching "Famine, Affluence, and Morality" by Peter Singer, I don't simply go through the premises of the arguments or have the students engage in a vague and undirected discussion. I ask the students to tally up how much they spend per month on various discretionary purchases. Then, I provide them with information sheets from OxFam and Doctors Without Borders and have them calculate how many lives they would save as a class if they decided to contribute that money to those organizations. Students often react strongly to this information and the essential part of the lesson is to direct this reaction productively towards the various philosophical points to be made concerning Singer's article. Then, we move to a conversation about the famous drowning-baby-in-the-pond case. Having the students do the work drives home Singer's point in a deep way, and it makes them responsible for understanding the argument. I then ask them for possible objections without going deeply into Singer's article. We go on to see how Singer has anticipated many of their objections and how this strengthens the effect of the paper. It decisively demonstrates a point that will be an important aspect of their own papers and of philosophical skill in general: the ability to imagine objections to your view and respond to them. Having students discover this aspect of those who do excellent philosophy moves the students far more than simply pointing it out. Furthermore, the fact that the philosophical lesson is tied to an issue of real world significance reinforces the idea that it is important to look at the world philosophically and consider the issues that that perspective raises.
Philosophy is not simply a set of questions and canonical texts. It is also a set of skills and sensitivities. It is easy to focus on a clever argument or a devastating objection, but it is much more difficult to help students develop the skills and sensitivities sufficiently that they can make those arguments and objections themselves. To accomplish that, a teacher must require that they be active and engaged learners, which will allow them to think like philosophers do. That is the kind of teaching that I find important and it's the kind of teaching I truly enjoy.
back to top
Teaching Experience
- Courses Taught
- Climate Justice (NUS) (syllabus, pdf)
- Justice and Emerging Technology (NUS) (syllabus, pdf)
- Global Governance (NUS) (syllabus, pdf)
- Politics of Nonviolence (NUS) (syllabus, pdf)
- Innovation for Climate Justice (Santa Clara) (syllabus, pdf)
- Global Justice (Stanford, with Alex Levitov) (syllabus, pdf)
- Contemporary Moral Problems (UW) (syllabus, pdf)
- Ethics of War and Peace (UW) (syllabus, pdf)
- Introduction to Social and Political Philosophy (UW) (syllabus, pdf)
- Other Teaching Experience
- Secondary Education, Social Studies (2003-2005)
- Kaplan Test Preparation (2006-2012)
- Center for Talented Youth (Summer 2007)
In the following courses, I was the primary instructor in charge of determining course themes and content, formulating syllabi, developing lesson plans, selecting course readings, and assessing student work. Click below to download the syllabus for each class.
Students will be able to: accurately characterize and evaluate our best theories of global and intergenerational justice; meaningfully apply and critique those theories in light of the unique features and challenges of climate change; develop and deploy these critical skills in evaluating and justifying a set of global regimes and institutions designed to balance appropriately between development and climate adaptation; develop their skills at writing thesis-driven, argumentative papers concerning normative topics in the context of climate policy.
This module examines moral and public policy challenges presented by emergent technologies that challenge notions embodied in current institutions and theories of what is natural and what is subject to human manipulation, and even create entirely new domains of human activity and interest. These new technologies operate globally and often rapidly, generating consequences far beyond the location of their users. The module studies how social and political institutions—new or old—structure, regulate, develop, and distribute these technologies in accordance with various conceptions of justice. Students will learn to: understand and competently deploy theories of global distributive justice and just war theory; critically evaluate these theories and their limitations in the face of new technological challenges; gain knowledge of the risks, benefits, and costs associated with specific, emerging technologies; develop their skill at writing thesis-driven, argumentative papers concerning normative topics in the context of technology-related public policy.
One purpose of this module is to familiarize students with the basic structure of an important and diverse set of global governance regimes. We will be looking at how refugees and the use of force is managed, how trade is regulated, and how global health and environmental sustainability is created or ignored.
However, we will not limit ourselves to understanding the details of specific governance regimes, we will be asking deeper, theoretical questions that will inform our critical engagement and evaluation of those regimes. What is globalization and what—if anything—makes our current globalization different from previous patterns of global trade and interaction? Should we regulate and structure globalization through global government or global governance? What role, if any, should democracy and human rights be playing in global governance? What are the moral justifications for current policies and how should we change them in order to make them more just? From where—if anywhere—do our current regimes receive their political authority or legitimacy?
This course will give students tools to critically evaluate global governance and think about the ways it might be or need be reformed. The goal, then, is to have students learn how to think about global governance rather than to offer an extended, encyclopedic list of the regimes themselves. Similarly, another goal of this class is to develop students' argumentative and critical thinking and reading skills, and the assessments in the course will reflect that goal.
"Politics of Non-Violence" is a discussion-oriented seminar course that will focus on three distinct elements. First, we will distinguish between different kinds of non-violent political movements. The most important conceptual distinction, which will structure the course, will be between pacifism and civil disobedience. Second, the course will familiarize students with the historical trajectory of paradigmatic non-violent movements, including those that were predicated on civil disobedience (US Civil Rights movement) and those that were more closely connected with pacifism (such as Gandhi's non-violent campaign for decolonization). Third, we will look at the distinct theoretical logics of civil disobedience and pacifism, developing accounts of when and whether these kinds of social movements are justified. This will involve a detailed consideration of the relationship between freedom and political authority as well as just war theory. We will also consider and evaluate contemporary movements that have been inspired by Gandhi and King.
By the end of the course, students should have substantive knowledge of concepts and debates relating to the use of nonviolence and of their development in key contemporary social movements. They should also have learned how to apply some of the methods and techniques of analysis that are important in analytic political theory, such as rigor, precision, textual interpretation, critical thinking, and clarity of expression and communication.
Climate justice is an ethical framework for evaluating the unequal distribution of climate-related harms on the poor, vulnerable, and socially marginalized – and for guiding interventions to overcome these injustices. Confronting global climate disruption is a major challenge for humanity. It threatens to roll back progress in global economic development for the poor, and undermine sustainable development goals. Innovation in its multiple forms holds out some promise for helping vulnerable communities adapt in a climate-disrupted world.
This course analyzes this distribution of current and anticipated global climate changes' impacts on the global poor, interrogates questions of distributive and procedural justice, and evaluates the potential of innovation and entrepreneurship to foster adaptation to climate disruption across the Global South. The conceptual domain of the course encompasses the intersection of climate ethics, political ecology/development studies, and science, technology, and society (STS)/innovation studies. It draws material from the SCU Global Social Benefit Institute's 200 case studies of social enterprises, working across the developing world. Of those 200 cases, about half promote frugal technologies to foster climate resilience in various forms. (Note that this course will not focus primarily on climate science, international climate treaty negotiations, North America/EU transition to a new climate economy, or climate engineering/geoengineering.)
As a result of this class, students will be able to: describe the scientific understandings of the current and anticipated impacts of global climate change in different regions; discuss factors that lead to the uneven distribution of climate change disruption; describe and explain the moral, ethical, and justice implications of climate disruption, adaptation, and resilience; critically analyze innovation and entrepreneurship as community-scale adaptation strategies to foster climate resilience among communities in the developing world; articulate strategies and a moral vision for fostering climate change adaptation grounded in an ethic of justice.
This course provides an introduction to ethical problems in contemporary international politics, with a special focus on the problem of global distributive justice. What duties do citizens in wealthy countries have to assist the global poor? What are human rights, and do they set meaningful limits to a state's liberty to govern its own affairs? Can changes in existing immigration restrictions or trade practices improve global justice? How should we distribute the burdens of environmental protection? What would it mean for existing international institutions to be made more democratic? We will approach these questions from a variety of disciplinary perspectives, drawing not only on the leading theoretical scholarship on the subject, but also on select historical cases and recent empirical contributions from economics and political science.
By the end of the course, students should have substantive knowledge of concepts and debates relating to global justice and of their development in key contemporary texts. They should also have learned how to apply some of the methods and techniques of analysis that are important in analytic political theory, such as rigor, precision, textual interpretation, critical thinking, and clarity of expression and communication.
Ethical reasoning is difficult. Our ethical obligations may require us to do things that are quite demanding, and disagreements about what is to be valued can be passionate and rancorous. This class will focus on getting students to engage in critical and productive reflection about ethical theories, particular ethical problems, and questions of value. To that end, this course will have several parts. First, we will discuss and evaluate various attempts to "shortcut" ethical theory: psychological egoism, divine command theory, and cultural relativism. Next, we will examine the two major ethical theories—utilitarianism and Kantianism—that have dominated philosophical thinking about morality. With these systematic theories on the table, we will analyze some complex ethical and social issues: abortion, aid to the global poor, prostitution and climate change.
The Just War Tradition has long been the dominant application of ethical theorizing to warfare. This tradition lays out moral principles that answer the following questions: when should one go to war, how should one behave when fighting a war, and how should one make peace? Yet, while this tradition has become deeply embedded in both international law and military practice, it has increasingly come under criticism that it is outdated and unresponsive to new forms of military conflict. According to critics, just war theory is obsolete in a world where states usually do not fight states. We now live in a world of insurgencies, counterinsurgencies, private militaries, drones, lawfare, humanitarian intervention, and transnational terrorism. The purpose of this class is to evaluate the extent to which these forms of military conflict put pressure on us to revise, or even reject completely, the just war tradition. In the process, we will discuss the moral issues surrounding recent military events: the NATO intervention in Libya, the defeat of the Tamil Tigers in Sri Lanka, and the targeted killing of Anwar Al-Awlaki in Yemen. We will also explore less mainstream views of morality of warfare, including realism and pacifism.
Markets are ubiquitous in our social and economic lives. They shape what projects we can pursue, aggregate information held by many people, and provide an outlet for individual choice. Increasingly, there have been calls to allow individuals greater choice by creating markets to govern areas of our lives—from public education to the environment to national security—where they had not previously existed. This class will be about the power and limits of individual choice and markets. We will explore why markets, under certain circumstances, are powerful tools, but we will also discuss when and why markets fail. Further, we will consider whether there are times when markets are morally inappropriate.
I received my certification in Secondary Education with a specialty in Social Studies from the Undergraduate Teacher Education Program at the Harvard Graduate School of Education. I taught American History in Boston and then taught American Government in Chicago. In Chicago, I also taught ESL social studies classes.
Over the course of six years, I taught over 20 courses in test preparation, covering the ACT, SAT, GRE, and LSAT. I tutored dozens of students and led seminars on writing personal statements and the law school admissions process.
I was a teaching assistant for an intensive Introduction to Formal Logic class for high-achieving middle school students.
back to top
Teaching Effectiveness
- Teaching Awards and Honors
- Philosophy Department Teaching Award, University of Washington
- Dean's Letter for Exceptional Teaching, University of Washington
- Incomplete List of Teachers Ranked as Excellent, University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign
- Pedagogy Chair, University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign
- Kaplan Teacher of the Year
- Kaplan Elite Teacher Status
- Student Evaluations
- Faculty Observations
The department grants this competitive award to one or two graduate students per year for excellence in the classroom. I won this award for the 2009-2010 academic year, primarily for my work as a teaching assistant for Philosophy of Human Rights and Introduction to Ethical Theories.
These letters are given in recognition of exceptional scores (normally 4.8 or higher out of 5) in the categories of 'Teaching Effectiveness' and 'Amount Learned' in the previous academic year. I have received this letter twice, for my teaching in the 2009-2010 and 2010-2011 academic years.
This list is compiled each semester by the Center for Teaching Excellence. It lists all instructors whose student evaluations place them in the top ten percent of teachers. I received this award for both semesters I was eligible to appear on the list.
My fellow graduate students elected me to this position for the 2006-2007 and 2007-2008 academic years.
This annual award is given according to instructional region and celebrates teachers who provide excellent individual assistance to students, exceptional teaching effectiveness, and impeccable corporate citizenship. I have received this award from both the Champaign and Seattle Kaplan Centers.
Award given to Kaplan instructors who, over the course of 50 student ratings, garner exceptional scores on teaching effectiveness. I have been awarded this status each time I've been eligible.
Available on request.
Available on request.
back to top